Lecture XX from MATHEMATICAL PHILOSOPHY*
1922
Korzybski's Concept of Man1
WHAT TIME-BINDING MEANS-DIMENSIONALITY AND THE MATHEMATICAL THEORY OF LOGICAL TYPES-THE NATURAL LAW OF CIVILIZATION AS AN INCREASING EXPONENTIAL FUNCTION OF TIME-HUMAN ETHICS AS TIME-BINDING ETHICS, NOT THE SPACE-BINDING ETHICS OF ANIMALS.
A FEW years ago our lives were lapt round with a civilization so rich and comfortable in manifold ways, so omnipresent, so interwoven with our whole environment, that we did not reflect upon it but habitually took it all for granted as we take for granted the great gifts of Nature,-land and sea, light and sky and the common air. We were hardly aware of the fact that Civilization is literally a product of human labor and time; we had not thought deeply upon the principle of its genesis nor seriously sought to discover the laws of its growth; we had not been schooled to reflect that we who were enjoying it had neither produced it nor earned its goods; we had not been educated to perceive that we have it almost solely as a bounty from the time and toil of by-gone generations; we had not been disciplined to feel the mighty obligation which the great inheritance imposes upon us as at once the posterity of the dead and the ancestry of the yet unborn. We had been born in the midst of a great civilization, and, in accord with our breeding, we lived in it and upon it like butterflies in a garden of flowers, not to say as "maggots in a cheese."
Since then a change has come. The [First] World War awoke us. The awakening was rude but it was effectual. Everywhere men and women are now thinking as never before, and they are thinking about realities for they know that there is no other way to cope with the great problems of a troubled world. They have learned, too, that, of all the realities with which we humans have to deal, the supreme reality is Man; and so the questions that men and women are everywhere asking are questions regarding Man, for they are questions of ethics, of social institutions, of education, of economics, of philosophy, of industrial methods, of politics and government. The questions have led to some curious results,-to doctrines that alarm, to proposals that startle,-and we are wont to call them radical, revolutionary, red. Is it true that our thinking has been too radical ? How the question would have made Plato smile-Plato who had seen his venerated teacher condemned to death for radical criticism. No, the trouble is that, in the proper sense of that much abused term, our thought has not been radical enough. Our questionings have been eager and wide-ranging but our thought has been shallow. It has been passionate and it has been daring but it has not been deep. For, if it had been deep, we could not have failed, as we have failed, to ask ourselves the fundamental question: What is that in virtue of which human beings are human? What is the distinctive place of our human kind in the hierarchy of the world's life ? What is Man ?
I have called the question "fundamental"-it is fundamental-the importance of a right answer is sovereign-for it is obvious, once the fact is pointed out, that the character of human history, the character of human conduct, and the character of all our human institutions depend both upon what man is and in equal or greater measure upon what we humans think man is.
Why, then, have we not asked the question? The reason doubtless is that we have consciously or unconsciously taken it for granted that we knew the answer. For why enquire when we are sure we know ?
But have we known? Is our assumption of knowledge in this case just ? Have we really known, do we know now, what is in fact the idiosyncrasy of the human class of life ? Do we know critically what we, as representatives of man, really are ? Here it is essential to distinguish; we are speaking of knowledge; there is a kind of knowledge that is instinctive,- instinctive knowledge,-immediate inner knowledge by instinct,-the kind of knowledge we mean when we say that we know how to move our arms or that a fish knows how to swim or that a bird knows how to fly. I do not doubt that, in this sense of knowing, we do know what human beings are; it is the kind of knowledge that a fish has of what fishes are or that a bird has of what birds are. But there is another kind of knowledge,-scientific knowledge,- knowledge of objects by analyzing them,-objective knowledge by concepts,-conceptual knowledge of objects; it is the kind of knowledge we mean when we say that we know or do not know what a plant is or what a number is. Now, we do not suppose fish to have this sort of knowledge of fish; we do not suppose a bird can have a just conception,-nor, properly speaking, any conception,-of what a bird is. We are speaking of concepts, and our question, you see, is this: Have we humans a just Concept of Man? If we have, it is reasonable to suppose that we inherited it, for so important a thing, had it originated in our time, would have made itself heard of as a grave discovery. So I say that, if we have a just concept of man, it must have come down to us entangled in the mesh of our inherited opinions and must have been taken in, as such opinions are usually taken in, from the common air, by a kind of "cerebral suction."
If we discover that we have never had a just concept of man, the fact should not greatly astonish us, for the difficulty is unique; man, you see, is to be both the knower and the object known; the difficulty is that of a knower having to objectify itself and having then to form a just concept of what the object is.
In saying that in the thought
of our time the great question has not been asked, I have now
to make one important exception and, so far as I know, only
one.2
I refer to Count Alfred Korzybski, the Polish engineer. In his
momentous book (The Manhood of Humanity: The Science and Art
of Human Engineering3), he has
both propounded the question and submitted an answer that is worthy
of the serious attention of every serious student, whatever his field
of study. It is the aim of this lecture to present the answer and to
examine it by help of the Theory of Logical Types, the Theory of
Classes, and the author's closely allied notion of "Dimensions."
Let me say at the outset that
one who would read the book understandingly must come to it prepared
to grapple with a central concept, a concept whose role
among the other ideas in the work is like that of the sun in the
solar system. It happens, therefore, that readers of the book,
or of any other book built about a central concept, fall into
three mutually exclusive classes:
(I) The class of those who
miss the central concept-(I have known a learned historian
to miss it) -not through any fault of their own,-they are often
indeed well meaning and amiable people,-but simply because they
are not qualified for conceptual thinking save that of the commonest
type.
(II) The class of those who
seem to grasp the central concept and then straightway
show by their manner of talk that they have not really grasped
it but have at most got hold of some of its words. Intellectually
such readers are like the familiar type of undergraduate who "flunks"
his mathematical examinations but may possibly "pull through"
in a second attempt and so is permitted, after further study,
to try again.
(III) The class of those who
firmly seize the central concept and who by meditating upon it
see more and more clearly the tremendous reach of its implications.
If it were not for this class, there would be no science in the
world nor genuine philosophy. But the other two classes are not
aware of the fact for they are merely "verbalists" In
respect of such folk, the "Behaviorist" school of psychology
is right for in the psychology of classes (I) and (II) there is
no need for a chapter on "Thought Processes"- it is
sufficient to have one on "The Language Habit."
What is that central concept
? What is Korzybski's Concept of Man? I wish to present it as
clearly as I can. It is a concept defining man in terms of Time.
"Humanity," says the author, "is the time-binding
class of life." What do the words mean? What is meant
by time-binding or the binding of time ? The meaning, which
is indeed momentous, will be clearer to us if we prepare for it
by a little preliminary reflection.
Long ages ago there appeared
upon this planet- no matter how-the first specimens of our human
kind. What was their condition? It requires some meditation and
some exercise of imagination to realize keenly what it must have
been. Of knowledge, in the sense in which we humans now use the
term, they had none-no science, no philosophy, no art, no religion;
they did not know what they were nor where they were; they knew
nothing of the past, for they had no history, not even tradition;
they could not foretell the future, for they had no knowledge
of natural law; they had no capital,-no material or spiritual
wealth,-no inheritance, that is, from the time and toil of by-gone
generations; they were without tools, without precedents, without
guiding maxims, without speech, without any light of human experience;
their ignorance, as we understand the term, was almost absolute.
And yet, compared with the beasts, they were miracles of genius,
for they contrived to do the most wonderful of all things that
have happened on our globe-they initiated, I mean, the
creative movement which their remote descendants call Civilization.
Why? What is the secret? Have
you ever tried to find it? The secret is that those rude animal-resembling,
animal-hunting, animal-hunted ancestors of ours were
a new kind of creature in the world-a new kind because
endowed with a strange new gift -a strange new capacity or power-a
strange new energy, let us call it. And it is in the world
today. What is it? We know it partly by its effects and partly
by its stirring within us for as human beings, as representatives
of Man, we all of us have it in some measure. It is the energy
that invents-that produces instruments, ideas, institutions and
doctrines; it is, moreover, the energy that, having invented,
criticizes, then invents again and better, thus advancing
in excellence from creation to creation endlessly. Be good enough
to reflect and to reflect again upon the significance of those
simple words: invents; having invented, criticizes; invents again
and better; thus advancing, by creative activity, from stage to
stage of excellence without end. Their sound is familiar; but
what of their ultimate sense? We ought indeed to pause here, withdraw
to the solitude of some cloister and there in the silence meditate
upon their meaning; for they do not describe the life of beasts;
they characterize Man.
We are speaking of a peculiar
kind of energy- the energy that civilizes-that strange
familiar energy that makes possible and makes actual the great
creative movement which we call human Progress, of which
we talk much and think but little. Let us scrutinize it more closely;
let us, if we can, lay bare its characteristic relation to Time
for its relation to Time is the relation of Time to the distinctive
life of Man.
Compare some representative
of the animal world, a bee, let us say, or a beaver, with a correspondingly
representative man. Consider their achievements and the ways thereof.
The beaver makes a dam; the man, a bridge or some discovery,-analytical
geometry, for example, or the art of printing, or the Keplerian
laws of planetary motion, or the atomic constitution of matter.
The two achievements,-that of the beaver and that of the man,-are
each of them a product of three factors: time, toil, and raw material,
where the last signifies, in the case of purely scientific achievement,
the data of sense, in which science has its roots. Both achievements
endure, it may be for a short while only,-as in the case
of the dam or the bridge,-or one of them may endure endlessly,-as
in that of a scientific discovery. What happens in the next generation
? The new beaver begins where its predecessor began and ends where
it ended-it makes a dam but the dam is like the old one. Yet the
old dam is there for the new beaver to behold, to contemplate,
and to improve upon. But the presence of the old dam wakes in
the beaver's "mind" no inventive impulse, no creative
stirring, and so there is no improvement, no progress. Why not?
The answer is obvious: the beaver "mind" is such
that its power to achieve is not reinforced by the
presence of past achievement. The new beaver's time is indeed
overlapped, in part or wholly, by the time of its predecessor
for the latter time is present as an essential factor of the old
dam, but that old-time factor, though present, produces
nothing-it is as dead capital, bearing no interest. Such is
the relation of the beaver "mind,"-of the animal
mind,- to time.
Now, what of the new man?
What does he do? What he does depends, of course, upon
his predecessor's achievement; if this was a bridge, he makes
a better bridge or invents a ship; if it was the discovery of
analytical geometry, he enlarges its scope or invents the calculus;
if it was the art of printing, he invents a printing press; if
it was the discovery of the laws of planetary motion, he finds
the law of gravitation; if it was the discovery of the atomic
constitution of matter, he discovers the electronic constitution
of atoms. Such is the familiar record-improvement of old
things, invention of new ones -Progress. Why ? Again
the answer is obvious: the mind of man, unlike animal "mind,"
is such that its power to achieve is reinforced by
past achievement. As in the case of the beaver, so in that of
man, the successor's time is overlapped by the predecessor's time
for the latter time continues its presence as an essential factor
in the old achievement, which endures; but,-and this is the point,-in
man's case, unlike the beaver's, the old-time factor
is not merely present, it works; it is not as dead capital,
bearing no interest, and ultimately perishing-it is living capital
bearing interest not only but interest perpetually compounded
at an ever-increasing rate. And the interest is growing wealth,-material
and spiritual wealth,-not merely physical conveniences but instruments
of power, understanding, intelligence, knowledge and skill, beautiful
arts, science, philosophy, wisdom, freedom-in a word, Civilization.
That great process,-involving
some subtle alchemy that we do not understand,-by which the time-factor,
embodied in things accomplished, perpetually reinforces more and
more the achieving potency of the human mind,-the process by which
mysterious Time thus continually and increasingly augments the
civilizing energy of the world,-the process by which the evolution
of civilization involves the storing up or involution of time,-it
is that mighty process which Korzybski happily designates by the
term, Time-binding. The term will recur frequently in our
discussion, and so I recommend that you dwell upon its meaning
as given until you have seized it firmly. It is because time-binding
power is not only peculiar to man but is, among man's distinctive
marks, beyond all comparison the most significant one-it is because
of that two-fold consideration that the author defines
humanity to be "the time-binding class of life."
Such, then, is Korzybski's
answer to the most important of all questions: what is Man? Do
not lose sight of the fact that we have here a concept and
that it defines man in terms of a certain relation, subtle indeed
but undoubtedly characteristic, that man has to time. By saying
that the relation is "characteristic" of man I mean
that, among known classes of life, man and only man has it. Animals
have it not or, if they have it, if they have time-binding
capacity, they have it in a degree so small that it may be neglected
as mathematicians neglect infinitesimals of higher order.
The answer in question is
not one to which the world has been or is now accustomed. If you
apply for an answer to the thought of the bygone centuries or
to the regnant philosophies of our time, what answer will you
get? It will be one or the other of two kinds: it will be a zoological
answer-man is an animal, a kind or species of animal, the
bête humaine; or it will be a mythological answer-man
is a mysterious compound or union of animal (a natural
thing) with something "supernatural." Such are the rival
conceptions now current throughout the world. They have come to
us as a part of our philosophical inheritance. Some of us hold
one of them; some of us, the other; and no doubt many of us hold
both of them for, though they are mutually incompatible, the mere
incompatibility of two ideas does not necessarily prevent them
from finding firm lodgment in the same brain.
That Korzybski's concept of
man is just and important,-entirely just and immeasurably important,
-I have no reason to doubt after having meditated much upon it.
But the author does not content himself with presenting that concept;
he goes much further; he denies outright the zoological conception
and similarly denies the ages-old rival, the mythological
conception, denouncing both of them as being at once false to
fact and vicious in effect.
Why false ? Wherein ?
Let us deal first with the
zoological or biological conception. Natural phenomena are to
be conceived and defined in accord with facts revealed by observation
and analysis. The phenomena the author is concerned with are the
great life-classes of the world: plants, animals, and humans.
What, he asks, are the significant facts about them, their patent
cardinal relations, their distinctive marks, positive and negative
? And his answer runs as follows: Of plants the most significant
positive mark is their power to "bind" the basic energies
of the world-to take in, transform and appropriate the energies
of sun, soil, water and air; but they lack autonomous power
to move about in space, and that lack is a highly significant
negative mark of plants. The plants are said to constitute the
"chemistry-binding" or basic-energy binding
class of life; the name suggests only the positive mark
but it is essential to note that the definition of the
class is effected by the positive and the negative marks conjoined.
What of the animals ? These, like the plants, take in, transform
and appropriate the basic energies of sun, soil, water and air,
taking them in large part as already transformed by the plants;
but this power of animals to bind basic energies,-the positive
one of the two defining marks of plants,-is not a defining
mark of animals; the positive defining mark of animals
is their autonomous power to move4 about
in space,-to crawl or run or fly or swim,-enabling them to abandon one
place and occupy another and so to harvest the natural fruits of many
localities; this positive mark, you observe, is a relation of animals
to space; but they have, we have seen, a negative mark, a relation
to time-animals lack capacity for binding time. Because of
the positive mark, animals are said to constitute the "space-binding"
class of life, but it is to be carefully noted that the definition
( as distinguished from the name) of the class is effected by
the positive mark conjoined with the negative one. Finally, what
of humans? We have already seen the answer and the ground thereof-humanity
is the time-binding class of life. For the sake of clarity
let us summarize the conceptions, or definitions, as follows:
a plant is a living creature having the capacity to bind basic
energies and lacking the autonomous ability to move in space;
an animal is a living creature having the autonomous ability to
move about in space and lacking the capacity for binding time;
a man, or a human, is a living creature having time-binding
power.
It is to be noted that, as
thus conceived, the great life-classes of the world constitute
a hierarchy arranged according to a principle which Korzybski
calls life-dimensions or dimensionality, as follows:
The plants, or basic-energy-binders,
belong to the lowest level or type of life and constitute the
life-dimension I.
The animals, or space-binders,
belong to the next higher level or type of life and constitute
the life-dimension II.
Human beings, or time-binders,
belong to a still higher level or type of life and constitute
the life-dimension III.
Whether there be a yet higher
class of life we do not know and that is why in the conception
of man no negative mark is present.
Now, it is, of course, perfectly
clear that, according to the foregoing conceptions or definitions,
the old zoological conception of man as a species of animal is
false, as the author contends. But may we not say that he is here
merely playing with words ? Is it not entirely a matter of arbitrary
definition ? Has he not, merely to please his fancy, quite willfully
defined the term "animal" in such a way as to exclude
humans from the class so defined? The answer is undoubtedly, No.
Of course, it goes without saying that we could, if we chose,
define the mere word "animal" or any other noun so as
to make it stand for the "class" of plants, elephants,
humans, jabberwocks and newspapers. But we do not so choose.
Why not? Because we desire
our definitions to be expedient, to be helpful, to serve
the purpose of rational thinking. We want them, in other words,
to correspond to facts. Let us, then, forget the word for a little
while and look at the facts. It is a fact that there is a class
of creatures having space-binding capacity but not time-binding
capacity; it is a fact that there is another class of creatures
having both kinds of capacity; it is a fact that the difference
between the two,-namely, the capacity for binding time,-is not
only beyond all comparison the most significant of the marks peculiar
to man, but is indeed the most significant and precious thing
in the world; it is, therefore, a fact that not only the interests
of sound ethics, but the interests of science, demand that the
two classes, thus distinct by an infinite difference of kind
of endowment, be not intermixed in thought and discourse;
it is a fact that use of the same term "animal" to denote
the members of both classes,-men and beasts alike,-constantly,
subtly, powerfully tends to produce both intellectual and moral
obfuscation; it is, therefore, a fact that the author's condemnation
of the zoological conception as false to fact is amply justified
on the best of grounds.
It is indeed true that humans
have certain animal organs, animal functions, and animal propensities,
but to say that, therefore, humans are animals is precisely
the same kind of logical blunder as we should commit if we said
that animals or humans are plants because they have certain organs,
functions and properties in common with plants; and the blunder
is of a kind that is fundamental-it is the kind which mathematicians
call the confusion of types or of classes and which Korzybski
calls the "mixing of dimensions." To say that humans
are animals because they have certain animal propensities is logically
on a par with saying that geometric solids are surfaces because
they have certain surface properties or with saying that fractions
are whole numbers because they have certain properties that whole
numbers have.
Why is it that people are
shocked on encountering for the first time a categorical denial
of their belief that man is a species of animal? Do they feel
that their proper dignity as human beings is thus assailed ? Is
it because the animal basis of their space-binding ethics
is being thus attacked ? Is it that a well-reasoned scientific
conviction is suddenly contradicted? I do not think the shock
is due to any of these things. It is, I believe, due simply to
the fact that an old unquestioned, uncriticized creed of that
great dullard,-Common Sense,-has been unexpectedly challenged.
For it is evident to common sense,-it is obtrusively evident to
sense-perception, -that humans have certain animal organs
and animal experience-they are begotten and born, they feed and
grow, have legs and hair, and die, all just like animals; on the
other hand, their time-binding faculty is not thus evident;
it is not, I mean, a tangible organ; it is an intangible
function, subtle as spirit; and so common sense, guided
according to its wont by the uncriticized evidence of sense, and
thoughtlessly taking for major premise the false proposition that
whatever has animal organs and propensities is an animal, concludes
that our human kind is a kind of animal. But in this matter, as
in so many others, the old dullard is wrong. The proper life of
animals is life-in-space; the distinctive life of humans
is life-in-time.
But why are mere concepts
so important ? Our lives, we are told, are not controlled by concepts
but by impulses, instincts, desires, passions, appetites. The
answer is: Because concepts are never "mere" concepts
but are, in humans, vitally connected with impulses, instincts,
desires, passions, and appetites; concepts are the means by which
Reason does its work, leading to prosperity or disaster according
as the concepts be true or false.
I have said that the ancient
and modern rival of the zoological conception of man is the mythological
conception according to which man is a mysterious compound or
hybrid of natural (animal) and supernatural. This conception might
well be treated today as it was treated yesterday by Plato ( in
the Timaeus, for example ) . "We must accept," said
he, "the traditions of the men of old time who affirm themselves
to be the offspring of the gods-that is what they say-and they
must surely have known their own ancestors. How can we doubt the
word of the children of the gods ? Although they give no probable
or certain proofs, still, as they declare that they are speaking
of what took place in their own family, we must conform to custom
and believe them."5 But this gentle irony,-the way of the
Greek philosopher, -is not the way of the Polish engineer. The
latter is not indeed without a blithesome sense of humor but in
this matter he is tremendously in earnest, and he bluntly affirms,
boldly and confidently, that the mythological conception of man
is both false and vicious. As to its validity or invalidity, it
involves, he says, the same kind of logical blunder as the zoological
conception-it involves, that is, a fatal confusion of types, or
mixing of dimensions. To say that man is a being so inscrutably
constituted that he must be regarded as partly natural (partly
animal) and partly supernatural (partly divine) is logically
like saying that a geometrical solid is a thing so wonderful
that it must certainly be a surface miraculously touched by some
mysterious influence from outside the universe of space. Among
the life-classes of the world, our humankind is the time-binding
class; and Korzybski stresses again and again the importance of
recognizing that time-binding energy and all the phenomena
thereof are perfectly natural-that Newton, for example,
or Confucius, was as thoroughly natural as an eagle or an oak.
What does he mean by "natural"
? He has not told us,-at all events, not explicitly,-and that
omission is doubtless a defect which ought to be remedied in a
future edition of the book.
You are aware that the terms
"nature" and "natural" are currently employed
in a large variety of senses-most of them so vague as to be fit
only for the use of "literary" men, not for the serious
use of scientific men. What ought we to mean by the term "natural"
in such a discussion as we are now engaged in? The question admits,
I believe, of a brief answer that is fairly satisfactory. Everyone
knows that the things encountered by a normal human in the course
of his experience differ widely in respect of vagueness and certitude;
some of them are facts so regular, so well ascertained, so indubitable
that they guide in all the affairs of practical life; they are
known facts, we say, and to disregard them would be to
perish like unprotected idiots or imbeciles; such facts are of
two kinds: facts of sense-perception, or of this and memory,
and facts of pure thought; the former are familiar in the moving
pageant of the world-birth, growth, death, day, night, land, water,
sky, change of seasons, and so on; facts of pure thought are not
so obtrusively obvious but there are such facts; one of them is-"If
something S has the property P and whatever has P has the property
P', then S has P'." Now, all such facts are compatible-each
of them fits in, as we say, with all the others. I take it that
what we ought to mean by natural is, therefore, this: Nature
(or the natural) consists of all and only such things
as are compatible (consistent) with the best-ascertained
facts of sense and of thought.
If that be what Korzybski
means by "natural,"- and I think it very probably is,-then
I fully agree with him that humans are thoroughly natural beings,
that time-binding energy is a natural kind of energy, and
that his strenuous objection to the mythological conception of
man is, like his objection to the zoological conception, well
taken. If it were a question of biological data, mere mathematicians
would, of course, like other sensible folk, defer to the opinion
of biologists; it is not, however, a question of biological data,
these are not in dispute; it is a question of the logical significance
of such data; and respecting a question of logic, even biologists,-for
they, too, are sensible folk,-will probably admit that engineers
and mere mathematicians are entitled to be heard.
In this connection I desire
to say that, for straight and significant thinking, the importance
of avoiding what Korzybski calls "mixing dimensions"
cannot be overstressed. The meaning of the term "dimensions"
as he uses it is unmistakable; he has not, however, elaborated
an abstract theory of the idea; such an elaboration would, I believe,
show that the idea is reducible or nearly reducible to that of
the Theory of Logical Types, briefly dealt with in a previous
lecture and fully outlined in the Principia Mathematica of
Whitehead and Russell; it is, moreover, very closely allied to,
if it be not essentially identical with, Professor J. S. Haldane's
doctrine of "categories" as set forth in his very stimulating
and suggestive book Mechanism, Life, and Personality (E.
P. Dutton and Co.) wherein the eminent physiologist maintains
that mechanism, life, and personality belong to different categories
constituting a genuine hierarchy such that the higher is not reducible
to the lower, that life, for example, cannot be understood fully
in terms of mechanism, nor personality in terms of life. It is,
you observe, an order of ideas similar to that of Korzybski's
thesis that humans can be no more explained in terms of animals
than animals in terms of plants or plants in terms of minerals.
And it is an order of ideas that recommends itself, to me at all
events, because it is fortified by the analogous consideration
that geometry cannot be reduced to arithmetic, nor dynamics to
geometry, nor physics to dynamics, nor psychology to physics.
It will, I believe, be a great advantage to science and to philosophy
to recognize that there exists, whether we will or no, a hierarchy
of categories and to recognize that, to an understanding of the
higher categories, the lower ones, though necessary, are not sufficient.
Is there not, indeed, a highly important sense in which the phenomena
of a higher category throw as much light upon those of a lower
as the latter throw upon the former? Who can deny that, for example,
dynamics illuminates geometry quite as much as geometry illuminates
dynamics?
In Korzybski's indictment
of the zoological and mythological conceptions of man there are,
we have seen, two counts: he denies that the conceptions
are true; and he denounces them as vicious in their effects, contending
that they are mainly responsible for the dismal things of human
history and for what is woeful in the present plight of the world.
Of the former count I have already spoken; respecting the latter
one, my convictions are as follows: ( I ) if humanity be not a
thoroughly natural class of life, the term "natural"
having the sense above defined, it is perfectly evident that there
never has been and never can be a system of human ethics having
the understandability, the authority, and the sanction of natural
law, and this means that, under the hypothesis, there never has
been and never can be an ethical system "compatible with
the best-ascertained facts of sense and of thought";
(2) if, although our human kind be in fact a thoroughly natural
class, we continue to think that such is not the
case, the result will be much the same-our ethics will continue
to carry the confusion and darkness due to the presence in it
of mythological elements; (3) on the other hand, so long as we
continue to regard man as a species of animal, the social life
of the world in all its aspects will continue to reflect the tragic
misconception, and our ethics will remain,-what it always has
been in large measure,-an animal ethics, space-binding ethics,
an ethics of might, of brutal competition, of violence, combat,
and war.
Why so much stress upon ethics
? Because ethics is not a thing apart; it is not an interest that
is merely coordinate with other interests; it penetrates them
all. Ethics is a kind of social ether which, whether it be good
or bad, sound or unsound, true or false, pervades life, private
and public, in all its dimensions and forms; and so, if ethics
be vitiated by fundamentally false conceptions of human nature,
the virus is not localized but spreads throughout the body politic,
affecting the character of all activities and institutions,-education,
science, art, philosophy, economics, industrial method, politics,
government, -the whole conduct and life of a tribe or a state
or a nation or a world. I hardly need remind you that only yesterday
the most precious institutions of civilization were in great danger
of destruction by a powerful state impelled, guided and controlled
by animalistic ethics, the space-binding ethics of beasts.
This is indeed an unforgettable illustration of the mighty fact,
before pointed out, that the character of human history, human
conduct and human institutions depends, not merely upon what man
distinctively is, but also in large measure, even decisively,
upon what we humans think man is. If a man or a state habitually
regards humanity as a species of animal, then that man or state
may be expected to act betimes like a beast and to seek justification
in a zoological philosophy of human nature.
In view of such considerations
it is a great pleasure to turn to Korzybski's concept of man,
for it is not only a noble conception, as none can fail to perceive,
but it is also, as we have seen, undoubtedly just. Nothing can
be more important. What are its implications? And what are its
bearings? You cannot take them in at a glance-meditation is essential;
but, if you will meditate upon the concept, you will find that
the body of its implications looms larger and larger and that
the range of its bearings grows ever clearer and wider. Indeed
we may say of it what Carlyle said of Wilhelm Meister: "It
significantly tends towards infinity in all directions."
Let us reflect upon it a little. We shall see that human history,
the philosophy thereof, the present status of the world, the future
welfare of mankind, are all of them involved.
The central concept or thesis
is that our human kind is the time-binding class of life;
it is, in other words, that there is in our world a peculiar kind
of energy, time-binding energy, and that man is its organ-its
sole instrument or agency. What are its implicates and bearings?
One of them we have already
noted. It is that, though we humans are not a species of animal,
we are natural beings: it is as natural for humans to bind
time as it is natural for fishes to swim, for birds to fly, for
plants to live after the manner of plants. It is as natural for
man to make things achieved the means to greater achievements
as it is natural for animals not to do so.
That fact is fundamental.
Another one, also fundamental, is this: time-binding faculty,-the
characteristic of humanity,-is not an effect of civilization but
is its cause; it is not civilized energy, it is the energy that
civilizes; it is not a product of wealth, whether material
or spiritual wealth, but is the creator of wealth, both material
and spiritual.
I come now to a most grave
consideration. Inasmuch as time-binding capacity is the characterizing
mark,-the idiosyncrasy,-of our human kind, it follows that to
study and understand man is to study and understand the nature
of man's time-binding energies; the laws of human nature
are the laws,- natural laws,-of these energies; to study time-binding
phenomena,-the phenomena of civilization,- and to discover their
laws and teach them to the world, is the supreme obligation of
scientific men, for it is evident that upon the natural laws of
time-binding must be based the future science and art of
human life and human welfare.
One of the laws we know now,-not
indeed precisely,-but fairly well,-we know roughly, I mean, its
general type,-and it merits our best attention. It is the natural
law of progress in time-binding-in civilization-building.
We have observed that each generation of (say) beavers or bees
begins where the preceding one began and ends where it ended;
that is a law for animals, for mere space-binders-there is
no advancement, no time-binding-a beaver dam is a beaver
dam-a honey comb a honey comb. We know that, in sharp contrast
therewith, man invents, discovers, creates; we know that inventions
lead to new inventions, discoveries to new discoveries, creations
to new creations; we know that, by such progressive breeding,
the children of knowledge and art and wisdom not only produce
their kind in larger and larger families but engender new and
higher kinds endlessly; we know that this time-binding process,
by which past time embodied as cofactor of toil in enduring
achievements thus survives the dead and works as living capital
for augmentation and transmission to posterity, is the secret
and process of progressive civilization-building. The question
is: What is the Law thereof-the natural law? What its general
type is you apprehend at once; it is like that of a rapidly increasing
geometric progression-if P be the progress made in a given
generation, conveniently called the "first," and if
R denote the ratio of improvement, then the progress made
in the second generation is PR, that in the third is
PR2,
and that made in the single Tth generation will be PRT-1.
Observe that R is a large number,-how large we do not know,-and
that the time T enters as an exponent-and so the expression
PRT-1 is called an exponential
function of Time, and it makes evident, even to the physical
eye, the involution of time in the life of man. This is an amazing
function, as every student of the Calculus knows; as T
increases, which it is always doing, the function not only increases
but it does so at a rate which itself increases according to a
similar law, and the rate of increase of the rate of increase
again increases in like manner, and so on endlessly, thus sweeping
on towards infinity in a way that baffles all imagination and
all descriptive speech. Yet such is approximately the law,-the
natural law, -for the advancement of Civilization, immortal offspring
of the spiritual marriage of Time and human Toil. I have said
"approximately," for it does not represent adequately
the natural law for the progress of civilization; it does not,
however, err by excess, it errs by defect; for, upon a little
observation and reflection, it is evident that R, the ratio
of improvement, is not a constant, as above contemplated, but
it is a variable that grows larger and larger as time increases,
so that the function PRT-1 increases
not only because the exponent increases with the flux of time,
but because R itself is an increasing function of time.
It will be convenient, however, and we shall not be thus erring
on the side of excess, to speak of the above-mentioned law,
though it is inadequate, as the natural law for the progress
of time-binding, or of civilization-making.
Hereupon, there supervenes
a most important question: Has civilization always advanced in
accord with the mentioned law? And, if not, why not? The time-binding
energies of mankind have been in operation long-300,000 to 500,000
years, according to the estimates of those most competent to guess-
anthropologists and paleontologists. Had progress conformed to
the stated law throughout that vast period, our world would doubtless
now own a civilization so rich and great that we cannot imagine
it today nor conceive it nor even conjecture it in dreams. What
has been the trouble? What have been the hindering causes ? Here,
as you see, Korzybski's concept of man must lead to a new interpretation
of history-to a new philosophy of history. A fundamental principle
of the new interpretation must be the fact which I have already
twice stated,-namely, that what man has done and does has depended
and depends both upon what man distinctively is and also, in very
great measure, upon what the members of the race have thought
and think man is. We have here two determining factors-what
man is and what we humans think man is. It is their joint
product which the sociologist or the philosophic historian must
examine and explain. In view of the second factor, which has hardly
ever been noticed and has never been given its due weight, Korzybski,
in answer to our question, maintains that the chief causes
which have kept civilization from advancing in accord with its
natural law of increase are man's misconceptions of man. All that
is precious in present civilization has been achieved, in spite
of them, by the first factor- by what man is-the peculiar organ
of the civilizing energies of the world. It is the second factor
that has given trouble. Throughout the long period of our race's
childhood, from which we have not yet emerged, the time-binding
energies have been hampered by the false belief that man is a
species of animal and hampered by the false belief that man is
a miraculous mixture of natural and supernatural. These are cave-man
conceptions. The glorious achievements of which they have deprived
the world we cannot now know and may never know, but the subtle
ramifications of their positive evils can be traced in
a thousand ways. And it is not only the duty of professional historians
to trace them, it is your duty and mine. Whoever performs the
duty will be appalled, for he will discover that those evils-the
evils of "magic and myth," of space-binding "ethics,"
of zoological "righteousness"-for centuries growing
in volume and momentum-did but leap to a culmination in the World
War, which is thus to be viewed as only a bloody demonstration
of human ignorance of human nature.
We are here engaged in considering
some of the major implicates and bearings of the new concept of
man. The task demands a large volume dealing with the relations
of time-binding to each of the cardinal concerns of individual
and social life-ethics, education, economics, medicine, law, political
science, government, industry, science, art, philosophy, religion.
Perhaps you will write such a work or works. In the closing words
of this lecture I can do no more than add to what I have said
a few general questions and hints.
Korzybski believes that the
great war marks the end of the long period of humanity's childhood
and the beginning of humanity's manhood. This second period, he
believes, is to be initiated, guided, and characterized by a right
understanding of the distinctive nature of Man. Is he over-enthusiastic?
I do not know. Time will tell. I hope he is not mistaken. If he
is not, there will be many changes and many transfigurations.
I have spoken of ethics and
must do so again, for ethics, good or bad, is the most powerful
of influences, pervading, fashioning, coloring, controlling all
the moods and ways and institutions of our human world. What is
to be the ethics of humanity's manhood? It will not be an ethics
based upon the zoological conception of man; it will not,
that is, be animalistic ethics, space-binding ethics, the
ethics of beasts fighting for "a place in the sun,"
the ethics of might, crowding, and combat; it will not be a "capitalistic"
ethics lusting to keep for self, nor "proletarian"
ethics lusting to get for self; it will not be an ethics
having for its golden rule the law of brutes- survival of the
fittest in the sense of the strongest. Neither will
it be an ethics based upon a mythological conception of
man; it will not, that is, be a lawless ethics cunningly contrived
for traffic in magic and myth. It will be a natural ethics because
based upon the distinctive nature of mankind as the time-binding,
-civilization-producing,-class of life; it will be, that
is, a scientific ethics having the understandability, the authority,
and the sanction of natural law, for it will be the embodiment,
the living expression, of the laws,-natural laws,-of the time-binding
energies of man; human freedom will be freedom to live in accord
with those laws and righteousness will be the quality of a life
that does not contravene them. The ethics of humanity's manhood
will thus be natural ethics, an ethics compatible with the best-ascertained
facts of sense and of thought-it will be time-binding ethics-and
it will grow in solidarity, clarity, and sway in proportion as
science discovers the laws of time-binding,-the laws,
that is, of civilization-growth,-and teaches them
to the world.
And so I am brought to say
a word respecting education. In humanity's manhood, education,-in
home, in school, in church,-will have for its supreme obligation,
and will keep the obligation, to teach the young the distinctive
nature of man and what they, as members and representatives of
the race of man, essentially are, so that everywhere throughout
the world men and women will habitually understand, because bred
to understand, what time-binding is, that their proper dignity
as humans is the dignity of time-binding life, and that for
humans to practice space-binding ethics is a monstrous thing,
involving the loss of their human birthright by descent to the
level of beasts.6 It is often said that
ethics is a thing which it is impossible to teach. Just the
opposite is true-it is impossible not to teach ethics, for the
teaching of it is subtly carried on in all our teaching, whether
consciously or not, being essentially involved in the teacher's
"philosophy of human nature." Every home or school in which that
philosophy is zoological is, consciously or unconsciously, a nursery
of animalistic ethics; every home or school in which there prevails a
mythological philosophy of human nature is, consciously or unconsciously,
a nursery of a lawless ethics of myth and magic. From time immemorial,
such teaching of ethics, for the most part unconscious, the whole
world has had. And we have seen that when such teaching becomes
conscious, deliberate, and organized, a whole people can be so
imbued with both the space-binding animal ethics of might
and the mythical ethics of Gott mit uns that their State
will leap upon its neighbors like an infuriated beast. Why should
we not learn the lesson which the great war has so painfully taught
regarding the truly gigantic power of education? If the accumulated
civilization of many centuries can be imperiled by ethical teaching
based upon a false philosophy of human nature, who can set a limit
to the good that may be expected from the conscious, deliberate,
organized, unremitting joint effort of home and school and press
to teach an ethics based upon the true conception of man as the
agent and organ of the time-binding, civilizing energy of
the world ? I cannot here pursue the matter further; but in closing
I should like to ask a few general questions-pretty obvious questions-indicating
roughly the course which, I believe, further enquiry should take.
What are the bearings of the
new concept of man upon the social so-called sciences of
economics, politics, and government?
Can the new concept transform
those ages-old pseudo-sciences into genuine sciences
qualified to guide and guard human welfare because based upon
scientific understanding of human nature?
In view of the radical difference
between the distinctive nature of animals and the distinctive
nature of man, what are likely to be the principal differences
between
Which of the two kinds of
government best befits the social regime of autocrats, or plutocrats,
and slaves? And which best befits the dream of political equality
and democratic freedom?
Which of them most favors
the prosperity of "Acquisitive Cunning" ? And which
the prosperity of Productive Skill?
Which of them is the most
friendly to the makers of wealth ? And which of them to
the takers thereof ?
Which of them most favors
"boss" repression of others? And which makes the best
provision for intelligent self-expression?
Which of them depends most
upon might and war ? And which upon right and peace ?
Which of them is government
by "politics," by politicians? And which of them by
science, by honest men who know?
If man's time-binding
energy, which has produced all the wealth of the world, both material
and spiritual wealth, be natural energy, and if, as is
the case, the wealth existing at a given moment be almost wholly
a product of the time and toil of the by-gone generations,
to whom does it of right belong? To some of the living?
To all of the living? Or to all of the living and the yet
unborn ? Is the world's heritage of wealth, since it is a natural
product of a natural energy and of time (which is natural), therefore
a "natural resource" like sunshine, for example, or
a newfound lake or land? If not, why not? What is the difference
in principle?
Are the "right of conquest"
and the "right of squatter sovereignty" time-binding
rights ? Or are they space-binding "rights" having
their sanction in animalistic "ethics," in a zoological
philosophy of human nature?
What are the bearings of the
new concept of man upon the theory and practice of medicine ?
Man, though not an animal, has animal organs and animal functions.
Are all the diseases of human beings animal diseases or are some
of them human diseases, disorders, that is, affecting humans
in their distinctive character as time-binders? Can Psycho-analysis
or Psychiatry throw any light upon the question?
And what of the power that
makes for righteousness? Religion, it would seem, has the seat
of its authority in that time-binding double relationship
in virtue of which the living are at once posterity of the dead
and ancestry of the unborn,-in the former capacity inheriting
as living capital the wealth of civilization from the time and
toil of by-gone generations,-in the latter capacity holding
the inheritance in trust for enlargement and transmission to future
man.
A final reflection: under
the doctrine outlined there lies an assumption-it is that, when
men and women are everywhere bred to understand the distinctive
nature of our human kind, the time-binding energies of man
will be freed from their old bondage and civilization will advance,
in accord with its natural law, in a warless world, swiftly and
endlessly. If the assumption be not true, great Nature is at fault
and the world will continue to flounder. Of its truth, there can
be only one test-experimentation, trial. The assumption appears
to be the only scientific basis of hope for the world. Must not
all right-thinking men and women desire ardently that this
noble assumption be tried?
1 Part of this lecture is
found in my Phi Beta Kappa address on The Nature of Man (Science,
Sept. 9, 1921) and some of it in an article by me in The Pacific
Review, Dec., 1921.
2 Since writing the foregoing
I have observed a learned discussion of the question by Professor
Wm. E. Ritter in an article, Science and Organized Civilization, in
the Scientific Monthly, Aug., 1917. Professor Ritter once more
defines man as a kind of animal but the distinctive marks of the
kind, as given by him, are so grave as to make one wonder why he
did not altogether drop the "animal" element from the definition.
3 E. P. Dutton & Company.
4 Do sessile animals really
constitute an exception? It can be shown, I think, that such animals
are space-binders in Korzybski's sense.
5 Jowett's translation.
6 In a recent bulletin of the
Cora L. Williams Institute for Creative Education, Miss Williams has
said, with fine insight, that "time-binding should be made the basis
of all instruction and The Manhood of Humanity a textbook in every
college throughout the world."
* Mathematical Philosophy is to
be republished in the Collected Works of Cassius J. Keyser, by
Scripta Mathematica, New York.